
Classical Statistics: Smoke and Mirrors
... selected "randomly". A never defined, and in fact meaningless word designed to bamboozle the natives. And it does. Just as it fools the statisticians themselves. By a similar bait and switch scam, classical statistics turns every problem of inference into an irrelevant problem of averages over all p ...
... selected "randomly". A never defined, and in fact meaningless word designed to bamboozle the natives. And it does. Just as it fools the statisticians themselves. By a similar bait and switch scam, classical statistics turns every problem of inference into an irrelevant problem of averages over all p ...
03 probability distributions
... Equally Likely Events • Equiprobable or Equally Likely Events: Events are said to be equiprobable when one does not occur more often than the others. • When an unbiased die is thrown any one of the six spots may appear. • When an unbiased coin is tossed either a head or a tail appears ...
... Equally Likely Events • Equiprobable or Equally Likely Events: Events are said to be equiprobable when one does not occur more often than the others. • When an unbiased die is thrown any one of the six spots may appear. • When an unbiased coin is tossed either a head or a tail appears ...
Inferential Statistics: A Frequentist Perspective
... • Q: Where does probability come from? • A: A random process • i.e., random sampling or randomization ...
... • Q: Where does probability come from? • A: A random process • i.e., random sampling or randomization ...
estat4t_0404 - Gordon State College
... Principle of Redundancy One design feature contributing to reliability is the use of redundancy, whereby critical components are duplicated so that if one fails, the other will work. For example, single-engine aircraft now have two independent electrical systems so that if one electrical system fai ...
... Principle of Redundancy One design feature contributing to reliability is the use of redundancy, whereby critical components are duplicated so that if one fails, the other will work. For example, single-engine aircraft now have two independent electrical systems so that if one electrical system fai ...
unit 6 Counting and probability
... Let A be the set of strings of ten which begin with 1010 and B be the set of strings of ten which end with 00. Note that A and B are not disjoint. For A, the first four bits can be chosen in only one way and each of the following six bits can be chosen in two ways, then A = 26 = 64. Similar for ...
... Let A be the set of strings of ten which begin with 1010 and B be the set of strings of ten which end with 00. Note that A and B are not disjoint. For A, the first four bits can be chosen in only one way and each of the following six bits can be chosen in two ways, then A = 26 = 64. Similar for ...
Section III Population distributions The Normal (Gaussian
... Suppose that the sample comes from a large population of patients. If we had the survival times of all patients in the population (i.e. all with stomach cancer) we could draw a histogram for the whole population. Since the population size is large, the class or bin sizes for the histogram could be s ...
... Suppose that the sample comes from a large population of patients. If we had the survival times of all patients in the population (i.e. all with stomach cancer) we could draw a histogram for the whole population. Since the population size is large, the class or bin sizes for the histogram could be s ...
[2013] “Not only defended but also applied”: The perceived
... extends to non-Bayesians like Efron (1986) and Fraser (2011). As noted above, it is our impression that the assumptions of the likelihood are generally more crucial—and often less carefully examined—than the assumptions in the prior. Still, we recognize that Bayesians take this extra step of mathema ...
... extends to non-Bayesians like Efron (1986) and Fraser (2011). As noted above, it is our impression that the assumptions of the likelihood are generally more crucial—and often less carefully examined—than the assumptions in the prior. Still, we recognize that Bayesians take this extra step of mathema ...
Basic Business Statistics, 10/e
... In this topic, you learn various counting rules for such situations. ...
... In this topic, you learn various counting rules for such situations. ...
CC1-3 PG Statistics and Probability
... two events. In this situation there are three events (cone, flavor, topping), so we will use a probability tree. There are four possible flavors, each with three possible cones. Then each of those 12 outcomes can have three possible toppings. There are 36 outcomes for the compound event of choosing ...
... two events. In this situation there are three events (cone, flavor, topping), so we will use a probability tree. There are four possible flavors, each with three possible cones. Then each of those 12 outcomes can have three possible toppings. There are 36 outcomes for the compound event of choosing ...
chance variability
... to the areas of the rectangles between 45 and 55 in the probability histogram. This is approximated by the area under the normal curve for the interval (44.5,55.5). In standard units this corresponds to the interval (-1.1,1.1), which has a probability of 72.87% according to the table. c) This time t ...
... to the areas of the rectangles between 45 and 55 in the probability histogram. This is approximated by the area under the normal curve for the interval (44.5,55.5). In standard units this corresponds to the interval (-1.1,1.1), which has a probability of 72.87% according to the table. c) This time t ...
LAB 3
... c) The C.L.T. is still true even if the Yi 's are from different probability distributions! All that is required for the C.L.T. to hold is that the distribution(s) have a finite mean(s) and variance(s) and that no one term in the sum dominates the sum. This is more general than definition II). 1) In ...
... c) The C.L.T. is still true even if the Yi 's are from different probability distributions! All that is required for the C.L.T. to hold is that the distribution(s) have a finite mean(s) and variance(s) and that no one term in the sum dominates the sum. This is more general than definition II). 1) In ...
Resurrecting logical probability
... There have been three main schools of thought as to the nature of logical or epistemic probability. According to the frequentists, it does not exist, and one can get by with only factual probability (whether factual probability itself is interpreted as relative frequencies, limits of relative freque ...
... There have been three main schools of thought as to the nature of logical or epistemic probability. According to the frequentists, it does not exist, and one can get by with only factual probability (whether factual probability itself is interpreted as relative frequencies, limits of relative freque ...
Probability interpretations

The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.