
6.1 Discrete and Continuous Random Variables
... the outcome. Calculator and computer random number generators will do this. The sample space of this chance process is an entire interval of numbers: S = {all numbers between 0 and 1} ...
... the outcome. Calculator and computer random number generators will do this. The sample space of this chance process is an entire interval of numbers: S = {all numbers between 0 and 1} ...
The Addition Rules
... 1. In a box there are 3 red pens, 5 blue pens, and 2 black pens. If a person selects a pen at random, find the probability that the pen is: a.)A blue or a red pen, b.) A red or a black pen. 2. A small automobile dealer has 4 Buicks, 7 Fords, 3 Chryslers, and 6 Chevrolets. If a car is selected at ran ...
... 1. In a box there are 3 red pens, 5 blue pens, and 2 black pens. If a person selects a pen at random, find the probability that the pen is: a.)A blue or a red pen, b.) A red or a black pen. 2. A small automobile dealer has 4 Buicks, 7 Fords, 3 Chryslers, and 6 Chevrolets. If a car is selected at ran ...
Bernoulli Trials and Expected Value
... • We roll three dice. If three of a kind show up, we get $10. If only two of a kind show up, we get nothing. If all three dice have distinct values, we pay $0.75. Is this a good game to play over time? ...
... • We roll three dice. If three of a kind show up, we get $10. If only two of a kind show up, we get nothing. If all three dice have distinct values, we pay $0.75. Is this a good game to play over time? ...
Reduction(7).pdf
... The observed outcome x is important because it reduces the uncertainty about which hidden variable underlies a particular token experiment, without eliminating it entirely. However, note that the payoff vector of h is independent of the outcome experimental x because the conditional payoffs are inde ...
... The observed outcome x is important because it reduces the uncertainty about which hidden variable underlies a particular token experiment, without eliminating it entirely. However, note that the payoff vector of h is independent of the outcome experimental x because the conditional payoffs are inde ...
COS513 LECTURE 8 STATISTICAL CONCEPTS 1. M .
... is subject to bias coming from the initial belief (the prior) that is formed (at least in some cases) without evidence. One approach to avoid setting arbitrary parameters is to estimate p(θ) from data not used in the parameter estimation. We delve deeper into this problem later. 2.2. Frequentist Sta ...
... is subject to bias coming from the initial belief (the prior) that is formed (at least in some cases) without evidence. One approach to avoid setting arbitrary parameters is to estimate p(θ) from data not used in the parameter estimation. We delve deeper into this problem later. 2.2. Frequentist Sta ...
Chapter 4: Probability Distributions
... In Bernoulli trials, one can get “s” with probability p and “f” with probability 1−p in every trial (i.e. Bernoulli trials can be thought of as “sample with replacement”) Consider a variation of the problem, in which there are total of only a outcomes available that are successes (have RV values = “ ...
... In Bernoulli trials, one can get “s” with probability p and “f” with probability 1−p in every trial (i.e. Bernoulli trials can be thought of as “sample with replacement”) Consider a variation of the problem, in which there are total of only a outcomes available that are successes (have RV values = “ ...
Lecture6_SP17_probability_combinatorics_solutions
... model that fits the data. • If a coin comes up 60 times in 100 trials, then the simplest hypothesis is that the coin is biased towards landing on heads. • However, suppose the coin looks exactly like other coins that, in our experience, are fair coins. • Now we have two sets of data: the results of ...
... model that fits the data. • If a coin comes up 60 times in 100 trials, then the simplest hypothesis is that the coin is biased towards landing on heads. • However, suppose the coin looks exactly like other coins that, in our experience, are fair coins. • Now we have two sets of data: the results of ...
Document
... The makers of a diet cola claim that its taste is indistinguishable from the full-calorie version of the same cola. To investigate, an AP® Statistics student named Emily prepared small samples of each type of soda in identical cups. Then she had volunteers taste each cola in a random order and try t ...
... The makers of a diet cola claim that its taste is indistinguishable from the full-calorie version of the same cola. To investigate, an AP® Statistics student named Emily prepared small samples of each type of soda in identical cups. Then she had volunteers taste each cola in a random order and try t ...
Section 5 - Introduction Handout
... The Central Limit Theorem states that if the probability interval does not contain the population mean and the sample size continues increase closer and closer to the population size then the probability will continue to decrease and get closer and closer to 0. ...
... The Central Limit Theorem states that if the probability interval does not contain the population mean and the sample size continues increase closer and closer to the population size then the probability will continue to decrease and get closer and closer to 0. ...
Classical Statistics: Smoke and Mirrors
... selected "randomly". A never defined, and in fact meaningless word designed to bamboozle the natives. And it does. Just as it fools the statisticians themselves. By a similar bait and switch scam, classical statistics turns every problem of inference into an irrelevant problem of averages over all p ...
... selected "randomly". A never defined, and in fact meaningless word designed to bamboozle the natives. And it does. Just as it fools the statisticians themselves. By a similar bait and switch scam, classical statistics turns every problem of inference into an irrelevant problem of averages over all p ...
Probability interpretations

The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.