• Study Resource
  • Explore
    • Arts & Humanities
    • Business
    • Engineering & Technology
    • Foreign Language
    • History
    • Math
    • Science
    • Social Science

    Top subcategories

    • Advanced Math
    • Algebra
    • Basic Math
    • Calculus
    • Geometry
    • Linear Algebra
    • Pre-Algebra
    • Pre-Calculus
    • Statistics And Probability
    • Trigonometry
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Astronomy
    • Astrophysics
    • Biology
    • Chemistry
    • Earth Science
    • Environmental Science
    • Health Science
    • Physics
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Anthropology
    • Law
    • Political Science
    • Psychology
    • Sociology
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Accounting
    • Economics
    • Finance
    • Management
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Aerospace Engineering
    • Bioengineering
    • Chemical Engineering
    • Civil Engineering
    • Computer Science
    • Electrical Engineering
    • Industrial Engineering
    • Mechanical Engineering
    • Web Design
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Architecture
    • Communications
    • English
    • Gender Studies
    • Music
    • Performing Arts
    • Philosophy
    • Religious Studies
    • Writing
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Ancient History
    • European History
    • US History
    • World History
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Croatian
    • Czech
    • Finnish
    • Greek
    • Hindi
    • Japanese
    • Korean
    • Persian
    • Swedish
    • Turkish
    • other →
 
Profile Documents Logout
Upload
MATH 105: Finite Mathematics 7
MATH 105: Finite Mathematics 7

Title A characterization of contiguous probability
Title A characterization of contiguous probability

... {Pn} and {Qn} are said to be contiguous if for any sequence {Tn} of ^-measurable rv's on 3C, Tn-*0 in PΛ-probability if and only if ΓΛ->0 in (^-probability. In order to avoid unnecessary repetitions, all limits are taken as {n}y or subsequences thereof, converges to infinity through the positive int ...
Statistics and Probability Les son
Statistics and Probability Les son

Probability and Probability Distribution
Probability and Probability Distribution

Arnie Pizer Rochester Problem Library Fall 2005
Arnie Pizer Rochester Problem Library Fall 2005

... 4. (1 pt) rochesterLibrary/setProbability10NormalDist/ur pb 10 4.pg Assume that the readings on the thermometers are normally idstributed with a mean of 0◦ and a standard deviation of 1.00◦ C. Find P15 , the 15th percentile. This is the temperature reading separating the bottom 15 % from the top 85 ...
Teacher Notes.doc - TI Education
Teacher Notes.doc - TI Education

MAT 211 - Final - Arizona State University
MAT 211 - Final - Arizona State University

Week 2: Conditional Probability and Bayes formula
Week 2: Conditional Probability and Bayes formula

Conditional Probability
Conditional Probability

A First-Order Conditional Probability Logic With Iterations
A First-Order Conditional Probability Logic With Iterations

Common Core State Standards for Mathematics High School
Common Core State Standards for Mathematics High School

... same as the probability of A, and the conditional probability of B given A is the same as the probability of B. ...
Common Core and PASS
Common Core and PASS

Z-scores and Probability
Z-scores and Probability

... A standard roulette wheel has 2 green spaces, 18 red spaces, and 18 black spaces. What is the probability of the wheel stopping on red? p(red) = 18 / 38 = 0.47 = 47% An illustration of how statistics show that betting on games of chance is usually not very smart… If you spin the roulette wheel 100 ...
Appendix C -- A Refresher on Probability and Statistics
Appendix C -- A Refresher on Probability and Statistics

+ Check your 6.2 Homework below:
+ Check your 6.2 Homework below:

Chapter 8: Introduction to Probability and Statistics
Chapter 8: Introduction to Probability and Statistics

problems with the Multiverse
problems with the Multiverse

IM_chapter6
IM_chapter6

... Now, P(O1) + P(O2) + P(O3) + P(O4) + P(O5) + P(O6) = 1 implies that c + 2c + 3c + 4c + 5c + 6c = 1, from which we get c = 1/21. Hence P(O1) = 1/21; P(O2) = 2/21; P(O3) = 3/21; P(O4) = 4/21; P(O5) = 5/21; P(O6) = 6/21. P(odd number) = 1/21 + 3/21 + 5/21 = 9/21 = 0.428571. P(at most 3) = 1/21 + 2/21 + ...
Bell-Boole Inequality: Nonlocality or Probabilistic Incompatibility of Random Variables?
Bell-Boole Inequality: Nonlocality or Probabilistic Incompatibility of Random Variables?

... part) results of purely probabilistic studies on the problem of probabilistic compatibility of a family of random variables. They were done during last hundred years. And they have the direct relation to Bell’s inequality. A priori studies on probabilistic compatibility have no direct relation to th ...
Appendix C - Rivier University
Appendix C - Rivier University

... If EC is the complement of E, then P(EC) = 1 – P(E) P(E  F) = P(E) + P(F) – P(E  F) If E and F are mutually exclusive (i.e., E  F = Ø), then P(E  F) = P(E) + P(F) If E is a subset of F (i.e., the occurrence of E implies the occurrence of F), then P(E)  P(F) If o1, o2, … are the individual outco ...
Alternative Axiomatizations of Elementary Probability
Alternative Axiomatizations of Elementary Probability

PDF
PDF

Grade 6 Mathematics Goal 4 - NC Department of Public Instruction
Grade 6 Mathematics Goal 4 - NC Department of Public Instruction

... Three fair coins are tossed at the same time. What is the probability that one of the coins will show heads and the other two will show tails? A ...
Introduction to Probability and Statistics Eleventh Edition
Introduction to Probability and Statistics Eleventh Edition

Language Modelling
Language Modelling

< 1 ... 98 99 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 ... 305 >

Probability interpretations



The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.
  • studyres.com © 2025
  • DMCA
  • Privacy
  • Terms
  • Report