* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Irrational square roots
Survey
Document related concepts
List of prime numbers wikipedia , lookup
Fermat's Last Theorem wikipedia , lookup
Wiles's proof of Fermat's Last Theorem wikipedia , lookup
Fundamental theorem of algebra wikipedia , lookup
Mathematical proof wikipedia , lookup
Collatz conjecture wikipedia , lookup
Transcript
Irrational square roots MichaΜ·l Misiurewicz (mmisiure@math.iupui.edu), Indiana University - Purdue University Indianapolis, Indianapolis, IN β In the classroom. Suppose you show your students the standard proof that 2 is irrational: Proof by contradiction. Suppose that β 2 is rational. Then we can write β 2 = π/π for some coprime positive integers π and π. This means that π2 = 2π2 . Thus, π2 is even, and therefore π is even. Hence, π = 2π£ for some positive integer π£. We get 4π£ 2 = 2π2 , so 2π£ 2 = π2 . By the same argument, this implies that π is even, which β contradicts the assumption that π and π are coprime. Therefore 2 is irrational. Of course, the same proof works for every prime π. To prove that β π is irrational, replace 2 by π and βevenβ by βdivisible by π.β You wonder whether your students understand this principle. After all, it is not clear that for a student the notions of βevenβ and βdivisible by πβ are similar. After β β you prove the irrationality of 2 in class, you ask your students to prove that 3 is irrational. One studentβs proof starts by distinguishing the cases of π and π even or odd. This cannot be correct, you think, but before you write a big red zero on the paper, you read the rest of the proof. Suppose that β 3 is rational. Then we can write β 3 = π/π for some coprime positive integers π and π. This means that π2 = 3π2 . If π is even, then π2 is even, so π is even β a contradiction. If π is even, then 3π2 is even, so π is even β another contradiction. Thus, both π and π are odd, so π = 2π£ + 1 and π = 2π€ + 1 for some nonnegative integers π£, π€. We get (2π£ + 1)2 = 3(2π€ + 1)2 , so 2π£ 2 + 2π£ = 6π€ 2 + 6π€ + 1. The left-hand side is even, while the right-hand side is odd β β a contradiction. Therefore 3 is irrational. 1 2 The proof is correct! Your student has earned a perfect score instead of 0, but did not learn what you wanted to teach. Next time you are teaching this course, you do not repeat your mistake! You ask yourself: for what prime numbers does this βeven-oddβ proof work? You easily see that it works for all integers congruent to 3 modulo 4. It is clear what you have to do. The smallest prime number larger than 2 but not congruent to 3 modulo 4 is 5. β Thus, you ask your students to prove that 5 is irrational. One student submits this solution: Suppose that β 5 is rational. Then we can write β 5 = π/π for some coprime positive integers π and π. This means that π2 = 5π2 . If π is even, then π2 is even, so π is even β a contradiction. If π is even, then 5π2 is even, so π is even β a contradiction. Thus both π and π are odd, so π = 2π£ + 1 and π = 2π€ + 1 for some nonnegative integers π£, π€. We get (2π£ + 1)2 = 5(2π€ + 1)2 , so π£ 2 + π£ = 5π€ 2 + 5π€ + 1. Now, π£ 2 + π£ = π£(π£ + 1). Either π£ or π£ + 1 is even, so π£ 2 + π£ is even. Similarly, π€ 2 + π€ is even. Therefore the left-hand side of the equality π£ 2 + π£ = 5π€ 2 + 5π€ + 1 is even, β while the right-hand side is odd β a contradiction. Therefore 5 is irrational. Not again! This time, as you can again easily check, the proof works for all π congruent to 5 modulo 8. You are desperate. What can you do? To check whether β your students understand the idea of the proof of irrationality of 2, what can you ask them to prove? Problem. For which odd numbers π can we prove that β π is irrational using the βeven-oddβ method? Let us translate the βeven-oddβ method into the rigorous language of mathematics. β Assume that π = π/π with (π, π) = 1. Then π2 = ππ2 . (1) 3 Depending on whether π is even or odd, we write π = 2π£ or π = 2π£ + 1; depending on whether π is even or odd, we write π = 2π€ or π = 2π€ + 1 We substitute those expressions in (1). This gives us 4 possibilities. Some of them lead immediately to a contradiction (an even number equals an odd number), some of them may require further analysis. βFurther analysisβ means that we continue the same procedure with π£, π€ instead of π, π, that is, π£ may be even or odd and π€ may be even or odd. Repeating this procedure β times amounts to considering 22β possibilities (although some may be ruled out earlier in the process): π β‘ π (mod 2β ) for some π β {0, 1, . . . , 2β β 1}, and π β‘ π (mod 2β ) for some π β {0, 1, . . . , 2β β 1}. In fact, many cases are ruled out because π and π are odd. Thus, our proof is successful if, for some β β₯ 1, all possibilities are ruled out, that is, the equation π 2 β‘ ππ 2 (mod 2β ) (2) has no solutions in odd π, π . When solutions exist, we continue to β + 1. Since π is odd, it has an inverse modulo 2β . Multiplying both sides of (2) by the square of this inverse, we get π‘2 β‘ π (mod 2β ). We see that our problem is equivalent to the following: For which odd π is there an β β₯ 1, such that for every π‘ we have π‘2 ββ‘ π (mod 2β )? Solution. As we have noticed already, the βeven-oddβ method works if π β‘ 3, 5, 7 (mod 8). We can also see this by observing that π‘2 β‘ 1 (mod 8) for all odd π‘. We will show that it does not work if π β‘ 1 (mod 8). That is, we show that if π β‘ 1 (mod 8) then for every β β₯ 1 there is π‘ such that π‘2 β‘ π (mod 2β ), and the βeven-oddβ proof will never terminate. Let π β‘ 1 (mod 8). Then for π‘ = 1 we get π β‘ π‘2 (mod 2β ) for β = 1, 2, 3. Now we apply induction. Namely, we show that if β β₯ 3 and π β‘ π‘2 (mod 2β ) then either π β‘ π‘2 (mod 2β+1 ) or π β‘ (π‘ + 2ββ1 )2 (mod 2β+1 ). Indeed, if π β‘ π‘2 (mod 2β ) then either π β‘ π‘2 (mod 2β+1 ) (and we are done), or π β‘ π‘2 + 2β (mod 2β+1 ). In the latter 4 case, since 2β β 2 β₯ β + 1 and π‘ is odd, (π‘ + 2ββ1 )2 β‘ π‘2 + 2β π‘ + 22ββ2 β‘ π‘2 + 2β π‘ β‘ π‘2 + 2β + 2β (π‘ β 1) β‘ π‘2 + 2β β‘ π (mod 2β+1 ). Thus, by induction we prove that for every β β₯ 1 there is π‘ such that π β‘ π‘2 (mod 2β ). This solves our problem. Theorem. The βeven-oddβ method of proving that β π is irrational works for an odd π if and only if π β‘ 3, 5, 7 (mod 8). Conclusion. To check whether your students understand the proof of irrationality of β 2, ask them to prove that β 17 is irrational.