
chapterP_Sec2
... that can’t be expressed as a ratio of integers. Hence, they are called irrational numbers. • It can be shown, with varying degrees of difficulty, that these numbers are also irrational: ...
... that can’t be expressed as a ratio of integers. Hence, they are called irrational numbers. • It can be shown, with varying degrees of difficulty, that these numbers are also irrational: ...
[Part 1]
... as a polynomial of degree i + j + 1 in n, and this mode of expression is useful, still the formula is rather clumsy and hard to recall. Below we shall show how the method of generating functions can be used to obtain elegant closed forms for (1.1) very quickly. The first of these uses the Stirling n ...
... as a polynomial of degree i + j + 1 in n, and this mode of expression is useful, still the formula is rather clumsy and hard to recall. Below we shall show how the method of generating functions can be used to obtain elegant closed forms for (1.1) very quickly. The first of these uses the Stirling n ...
Threshold in N(n,p)
... We are interested in the threshold for when there is an arithmetic progression of length k. Where the arithmetic progression looks as: a, a+b, a+2b, a+3b; all of which are elements of the progression set. Let Xk be the number of arithmetic progressions of length k: E(Xk)=n2pk This is justified by th ...
... We are interested in the threshold for when there is an arithmetic progression of length k. Where the arithmetic progression looks as: a, a+b, a+2b, a+3b; all of which are elements of the progression set. Let Xk be the number of arithmetic progressions of length k: E(Xk)=n2pk This is justified by th ...
Foundations of the golden ratio base
... extended base-φ representation this process will eventually terminate. This first part is analogous to “carrying” in standard addition, with the exception that we must carry to two different places as opposed simply directly to left as in base-10. The second part of the process involves canceling ou ...
... extended base-φ representation this process will eventually terminate. This first part is analogous to “carrying” in standard addition, with the exception that we must carry to two different places as opposed simply directly to left as in base-10. The second part of the process involves canceling ou ...
Non-standard analysis

The history of calculus is fraught with philosophical debates about the meaning and logical validity of fluxions or infinitesimal numbers. The standard way to resolve these debates is to define the operations of calculus using epsilon–delta procedures rather than infinitesimals. Non-standard analysis instead reformulates the calculus using a logically rigorous notion of infinitesimal numbers.Non-standard analysis was originated in the early 1960s by the mathematician Abraham Robinson. He wrote:[...] the idea of infinitely small or infinitesimal quantities seems to appeal naturally to our intuition. At any rate, the use of infinitesimals was widespread during the formative stages of the Differential and Integral Calculus. As for the objection [...] that the distance between two distinct real numbers cannot be infinitely small, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz argued that the theory of infinitesimals implies the introduction of ideal numbers which might be infinitely small or infinitely large compared with the real numbers but which were to possess the same properties as the latterRobinson argued that this law of continuity of Leibniz's is a precursor of the transfer principle. Robinson continued:However, neither he nor his disciples and successors were able to give a rational development leading up to a system of this sort. As a result, the theory of infinitesimals gradually fell into disrepute and was replaced eventually by the classical theory of limits.Robinson continues:It is shown in this book that Leibniz's ideas can be fully vindicated and that they lead to a novel and fruitful approach to classical Analysis and to many other branches of mathematics. The key to our method is provided by the detailed analysis of the relation between mathematical languages and mathematical structures which lies at the bottom of contemporary model theory.In 1973, intuitionist Arend Heyting praised non-standard analysis as ""a standard model of important mathematical research"".