
"Week 6" notes with annotations made in lecture on Wednesday
... This no longer seems a city living in fear as it was in 2005 when gang warfare spilled out into the streets in the “summer of the gun.” The city s 32nd homicide occurred on Tuesday, compared to 38 at this time last year. With only four months to go in 2011, Toronto is on pace to record its lowest ho ...
... This no longer seems a city living in fear as it was in 2005 when gang warfare spilled out into the streets in the “summer of the gun.” The city s 32nd homicide occurred on Tuesday, compared to 38 at this time last year. With only four months to go in 2011, Toronto is on pace to record its lowest ho ...
Three Ways to Give a Probability Assignment a Memory
... magnitude of the initial probabilities of propositions that entail not-P & not-Q lives in infinitesimals of the order i2. This strategy of probability kinematics with infinitesimals gives probability distributions a memory that is almost as good as that supplied by Tait's suggestion.3 It has the adv ...
... magnitude of the initial probabilities of propositions that entail not-P & not-Q lives in infinitesimals of the order i2. This strategy of probability kinematics with infinitesimals gives probability distributions a memory that is almost as good as that supplied by Tait's suggestion.3 It has the adv ...
CS 547 Lecture 9: Conditional Probabilities and the Memoryless
... 1 Of course, the time between real bus arrivals is never exponentially distributed. People want to know exactly when their buses will come, so bus schedules are nearly deterministic, which justifies our intuition about longer waiting times increasing the probability of an arrival. ...
... 1 Of course, the time between real bus arrivals is never exponentially distributed. People want to know exactly when their buses will come, so bus schedules are nearly deterministic, which justifies our intuition about longer waiting times increasing the probability of an arrival. ...
Document
... The Chain Rule of Conditional Probabilities • Any joint probability distribution over many random variables may be decomposed into conditional distributions over only one variable ...
... The Chain Rule of Conditional Probabilities • Any joint probability distribution over many random variables may be decomposed into conditional distributions over only one variable ...
High School Cluster Quiz Probability
... 2 points: Writes 40.2% (a.) and an number in the interval 62% to 62.1%, inclusive (b.) AND Explains how the probabilities can be used to show there were fewer passengers in first class who did not survive than passengers who survived and were not in first class. Example: There were fewer passengers ...
... 2 points: Writes 40.2% (a.) and an number in the interval 62% to 62.1%, inclusive (b.) AND Explains how the probabilities can be used to show there were fewer passengers in first class who did not survive than passengers who survived and were not in first class. Example: There were fewer passengers ...
Lecture 3. Combinatorial Constructions Many probability spaces
... second, n − 2 for the third, etc. Therefore the total number of possible rearrangements is n! = n · (n − 1) · (n − 2) · · · · · 3 · 2 · 1. Fact 1. There are n! ways of arranging n distinct elements in order. Consider an experiment consists in rearranging an n-element set randomly in such a way that ...
... second, n − 2 for the third, etc. Therefore the total number of possible rearrangements is n! = n · (n − 1) · (n − 2) · · · · · 3 · 2 · 1. Fact 1. There are n! ways of arranging n distinct elements in order. Consider an experiment consists in rearranging an n-element set randomly in such a way that ...
Stat 31-Sect 3 (Spring 2001) Midterm Exam 2
... 3. The probability that Bob plays soccer on any given Saturday is 0.70, and the chance of rain is 0.25, as on any other day. Given that it is raining, the probability that Bob plays soccer is only 0.20.What is the chance that Bob plays and it rains on the same ...
... 3. The probability that Bob plays soccer on any given Saturday is 0.70, and the chance of rain is 0.25, as on any other day. Given that it is raining, the probability that Bob plays soccer is only 0.20.What is the chance that Bob plays and it rains on the same ...
View/Download PDF - Digital Learning Department
... and interpret the answer in terms of the model (+) Apply the general Multiplication Rule in a uniform probability model, P(A and B) = P(A)P(B|A) = P(B)P(A|B), and interpret the answer in terms of the ...
... and interpret the answer in terms of the model (+) Apply the general Multiplication Rule in a uniform probability model, P(A and B) = P(A)P(B|A) = P(B)P(A|B), and interpret the answer in terms of the ...
Computing Probabilities: Right Ways and Wrong Ways
... to toss heads, 1/6 to roll a 6, and 1/38 to get the number 29 in roulette (an American roulette wheel has the numbers 1–36, 0, and 00). Pure and simple. We can also compute probabilities of groups of outcomes. For example, what is the probability to get an odd number when rolling a die? As there are ...
... to toss heads, 1/6 to roll a 6, and 1/38 to get the number 29 in roulette (an American roulette wheel has the numbers 1–36, 0, and 00). Pure and simple. We can also compute probabilities of groups of outcomes. For example, what is the probability to get an odd number when rolling a die? As there are ...
Probability
... Denition 6. Consider an experiment whose outcome depends on chance. We represent the outcome of the experiment by a capital Roman letter, such as X , called a random variable. The sample space of the experiment is the set of all possible outcomes. If the sample space is either nite or countably in ...
... Denition 6. Consider an experiment whose outcome depends on chance. We represent the outcome of the experiment by a capital Roman letter, such as X , called a random variable. The sample space of the experiment is the set of all possible outcomes. If the sample space is either nite or countably in ...
discrete probability distributions
... 3. known p? same for each trial? for first trial p = 2/3 if no -second trial p =1 if yes -second trial p =1/2 4. trials are independent? ...
... 3. known p? same for each trial? for first trial p = 2/3 if no -second trial p =1 if yes -second trial p =1/2 4. trials are independent? ...
Continuous Probability Distributions
... MGMT 201: Statistics Continuous Probability Distributions (ASW Chapter 6) What do we mean when we say continuous random variable? Roughly speaking, a continuous random variable is one for which we cannot devise some method for counting the possible outcomes. Note that this specifically requires ha ...
... MGMT 201: Statistics Continuous Probability Distributions (ASW Chapter 6) What do we mean when we say continuous random variable? Roughly speaking, a continuous random variable is one for which we cannot devise some method for counting the possible outcomes. Note that this specifically requires ha ...
Probability interpretations

The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.