
Discrete probability
... This generalises: if A1 , . . . , An are events that are disjoint from each other, then P (A1 ∪ . . . ∪ An ) = P (A1 ) + . . . + P (An ). A function P with domain the set of events, and satisfying (1) and (2), is called a probability function. ...
... This generalises: if A1 , . . . , An are events that are disjoint from each other, then P (A1 ∪ . . . ∪ An ) = P (A1 ) + . . . + P (An ). A function P with domain the set of events, and satisfying (1) and (2), is called a probability function. ...
Original PowerPoint
... the multiplication principle, permutations, and combinations, we can figure out the probability of a certain outcome for probabilistic experiments. CSCI 1900 – Discrete Structures ...
... the multiplication principle, permutations, and combinations, we can figure out the probability of a certain outcome for probabilistic experiments. CSCI 1900 – Discrete Structures ...
Probability Sample Unit With Answers
... 23. A bag contains six blue marbles, seven red marbles, and four green marbles. If four marbles are drawn randomly without replacement, determine the probability that three are green. 24. A bag contains 3 green blocks, 5 purple blocks, and 6 red blocks. If four blocks are drawn one at a ...
... 23. A bag contains six blue marbles, seven red marbles, and four green marbles. If four marbles are drawn randomly without replacement, determine the probability that three are green. 24. A bag contains 3 green blocks, 5 purple blocks, and 6 red blocks. If four blocks are drawn one at a ...
chapter 2((probability theory ))
... The variants totaling twenty points are of the type A + 9 or 10 + 10 (as a value; that is, any 2-size combination of cards from 10, J, Q, K). We have sixteen variants A + 9 (4 aces and 4 nines) and C(16, 2) = 120 variants 10 + 10 (all 2-size combinations of cards from the sixteen cards with a value ...
... The variants totaling twenty points are of the type A + 9 or 10 + 10 (as a value; that is, any 2-size combination of cards from 10, J, Q, K). We have sixteen variants A + 9 (4 aces and 4 nines) and C(16, 2) = 120 variants 10 + 10 (all 2-size combinations of cards from the sixteen cards with a value ...
Math 20 Probability Review Spring 2017 1. Find the value of k that
... 7. Psychologists have determined that the time it takes a rat to find its way through a maze is exponentially distributed. Let x be the time in seconds, and for a particular maze the probability density function is f ( x) 0.025e0.025 x seconds, x 0 . (Note: an exponential pdf) a. Find the proba ...
... 7. Psychologists have determined that the time it takes a rat to find its way through a maze is exponentially distributed. Let x be the time in seconds, and for a particular maze the probability density function is f ( x) 0.025e0.025 x seconds, x 0 . (Note: an exponential pdf) a. Find the proba ...
Sample Midterm 1 (rev 14 Feb) with answers
... whether B or ~B occurs. For example, the outcome of a second coin flip is just as likely to be 'heads' regardless of whether the first coin flip is 'heads' or 'tails'. Option i is the Addition Rule for Mutually Exclusive Events. Mutually exclusive events are not independent, because one event's occu ...
... whether B or ~B occurs. For example, the outcome of a second coin flip is just as likely to be 'heads' regardless of whether the first coin flip is 'heads' or 'tails'. Option i is the Addition Rule for Mutually Exclusive Events. Mutually exclusive events are not independent, because one event's occu ...
Probability interpretations

The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.