
1 Axioms of probability, disjoint and independent events 2
... 9. You are dealt 6 cards from a standard deck of 52 cards. What is the probability that you get a four-of-a-kind and two cards that don’t match. For example, you could get 4 Kings, a 10 and a 3. But you couldn’t get 4 Kings and two 10s. 10. A licence plate consists of 3 letters followed by 3 number ...
... 9. You are dealt 6 cards from a standard deck of 52 cards. What is the probability that you get a four-of-a-kind and two cards that don’t match. For example, you could get 4 Kings, a 10 and a 3. But you couldn’t get 4 Kings and two 10s. 10. A licence plate consists of 3 letters followed by 3 number ...
Common Core Map Algebra 1B
... 1. Describe events as subsets of a sample space (the set of outcomes) using characteristics (or categories) of the outcomes, or as unions, intersections, or complements of other events (“or,” “and,” “not”). 2. Understand that two events A and B are independent if the probability of A and B occurring ...
... 1. Describe events as subsets of a sample space (the set of outcomes) using characteristics (or categories) of the outcomes, or as unions, intersections, or complements of other events (“or,” “and,” “not”). 2. Understand that two events A and B are independent if the probability of A and B occurring ...
L2 NUMERACY Unit 6
... Use the timetable to record whether the bus or train is late/on time/early over a number of occasions. You will need to decide exactly what ‘on time’ means and how you will know this. You will also need to decide on how many ‘occasions’ you are going to record this information. To what extent would ...
... Use the timetable to record whether the bus or train is late/on time/early over a number of occasions. You will need to decide exactly what ‘on time’ means and how you will know this. You will also need to decide on how many ‘occasions’ you are going to record this information. To what extent would ...
hca04_0807
... Probability of an Event E In a sample space with equally likely outcomes, the probability of an event E, written P(E), is the ratio of the number of outcomes in sample space S that belong to E, n(E), to the total number of outcomes in sample space S, n(S). That is, ...
... Probability of an Event E In a sample space with equally likely outcomes, the probability of an event E, written P(E), is the ratio of the number of outcomes in sample space S that belong to E, n(E), to the total number of outcomes in sample space S, n(S). That is, ...
A Simple Example Sample Space and Event Tree Diagram Tree
... What is the probability of getting two 6’s in casting a balanced die 5 times experiment? P(S∩S∩S’∩S’∩S’) = (1/6)2 x (5/6)3 = 0.016 P(S∩S’∩S∩S’∩S’) = (1/6)2 x (5/6)3 P(S∩S’∩S’∩S∩S’) = (1/6)2 x (5/6)3 ...
... What is the probability of getting two 6’s in casting a balanced die 5 times experiment? P(S∩S∩S’∩S’∩S’) = (1/6)2 x (5/6)3 = 0.016 P(S∩S’∩S∩S’∩S’) = (1/6)2 x (5/6)3 P(S∩S’∩S’∩S∩S’) = (1/6)2 x (5/6)3 ...
Random Variables and Discrete Probability Distributions
... important, yet uncertainty is a constant in any situation. No matter how well-calibrated a machine is, it is impossible to predict with absolute certainty how much part-to-part variation it will generate. Based on statistical analysis, an estimation can be made to have an approximate pp idea about t ...
... important, yet uncertainty is a constant in any situation. No matter how well-calibrated a machine is, it is impossible to predict with absolute certainty how much part-to-part variation it will generate. Based on statistical analysis, an estimation can be made to have an approximate pp idea about t ...
MAP estimator for the coin toss problem
... • Even though the ML estimator might say ML 0 , we “know” that the coin can come up both heads and tails, i.e.: 0 • Starting point for our consideration is that is not only a number, but we will give a full probability distribution function •Suppose we know that the coin is either fair ( ...
... • Even though the ML estimator might say ML 0 , we “know” that the coin can come up both heads and tails, i.e.: 0 • Starting point for our consideration is that is not only a number, but we will give a full probability distribution function •Suppose we know that the coin is either fair ( ...
4 CHAPTER SUMMARY
... 17. Can a binomial experiment be used to find the probability of 6 outcomes of A, 10 outcomes of B, and 4 outcomes of C? Explain your reasoning. 18. Can a binomial experiment be used to find the probability of 4 outcomes of C and 16 outcomes that are not C? Explain your reasoning. What is the probab ...
... 17. Can a binomial experiment be used to find the probability of 6 outcomes of A, 10 outcomes of B, and 4 outcomes of C? Explain your reasoning. 18. Can a binomial experiment be used to find the probability of 4 outcomes of C and 16 outcomes that are not C? Explain your reasoning. What is the probab ...
Intuitive Deduction and Approximation of the Binomial Distribution
... depending partially on chance, simple numbers are not an adequate model in the intent to overview the data. Suitable models are essential to simulate and overview a given situation or data efficiently. So instead of usage of simple numbers, probability in general and probability distributions are us ...
... depending partially on chance, simple numbers are not an adequate model in the intent to overview the data. Suitable models are essential to simulate and overview a given situation or data efficiently. So instead of usage of simple numbers, probability in general and probability distributions are us ...
Lecture Notes on Finite Probability Spaces
... What we call these two elements is not especially relevant; we could just as well call them 0 and 1. Perhaps there is a remote possibility that the coin will land on its edge. By modeling the experiment with the sample space {H, T }, we are excluding this possibility, essentially treating such an ou ...
... What we call these two elements is not especially relevant; we could just as well call them 0 and 1. Perhaps there is a remote possibility that the coin will land on its edge. By modeling the experiment with the sample space {H, T }, we are excluding this possibility, essentially treating such an ou ...
Probability interpretations

The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.