• Study Resource
  • Explore
    • Arts & Humanities
    • Business
    • Engineering & Technology
    • Foreign Language
    • History
    • Math
    • Science
    • Social Science

    Top subcategories

    • Advanced Math
    • Algebra
    • Basic Math
    • Calculus
    • Geometry
    • Linear Algebra
    • Pre-Algebra
    • Pre-Calculus
    • Statistics And Probability
    • Trigonometry
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Astronomy
    • Astrophysics
    • Biology
    • Chemistry
    • Earth Science
    • Environmental Science
    • Health Science
    • Physics
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Anthropology
    • Law
    • Political Science
    • Psychology
    • Sociology
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Accounting
    • Economics
    • Finance
    • Management
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Aerospace Engineering
    • Bioengineering
    • Chemical Engineering
    • Civil Engineering
    • Computer Science
    • Electrical Engineering
    • Industrial Engineering
    • Mechanical Engineering
    • Web Design
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Architecture
    • Communications
    • English
    • Gender Studies
    • Music
    • Performing Arts
    • Philosophy
    • Religious Studies
    • Writing
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Ancient History
    • European History
    • US History
    • World History
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Croatian
    • Czech
    • Finnish
    • Greek
    • Hindi
    • Japanese
    • Korean
    • Persian
    • Swedish
    • Turkish
    • other →
 
Profile Documents Logout
Upload
Teacher Version
Teacher Version

Document
Document

... We call this a "good" fit since the probability is close to 100%. If however the c2 was large (e.g. 15), the probability would be small (≈ 0.2% for 3 dof). We would say this was a “bad” fit. RULE OF THUMB A “good” fit has c2 /dof ≤ 1 ...
Lesson #70 – Theoretical and Empirical Probability
Lesson #70 – Theoretical and Empirical Probability

I. Chapter 1 Introduction to Probability Theory I.1. Case Study I.2
I. Chapter 1 Introduction to Probability Theory I.1. Case Study I.2

... -John Maynard Keynes (England, 1883-1946) People talk loosely about chance all the time, without doing any harm. What are the chances of getting a job? of meeting someone? of rain tomorrow? of passing Math. 3610? But for scientific purposes, it is necessary to give the word chance a definite, clear ...
GTS 111 Practice Final Exam
GTS 111 Practice Final Exam

Probability
Probability

Chapter 3: Probability - users.miamioh.edu
Chapter 3: Probability - users.miamioh.edu

framework for teacher knowledge and understanding about probability
framework for teacher knowledge and understanding about probability

Elementary Probability
Elementary Probability

... HT, TH, and TT This can be depicted graphically as follows. . . ...
Probability and Statistics
Probability and Statistics

Combinations and Permutations
Combinations and Permutations

... Experiments, Sample Spaces and Events An EXPERIMENT is any activity with an observable result. Tossing a coin, rolling a die or choosing a card are all considered experiments. An OUTCOME (or SAMPLE POINT) is the result of a the experiment. The set of all possible outcomes or sample points of an exp ...
Counting Random Events, 1 - Cosmic Ray Observatory Project
Counting Random Events, 1 - Cosmic Ray Observatory Project

Some initial plots comparing different scenarios
Some initial plots comparing different scenarios

y - Lake-Sumter State College
y - Lake-Sumter State College

Masses of Formal Philosophy `Interview`
Masses of Formal Philosophy `Interview`

Basic Review of Punnett Square
Basic Review of Punnett Square

Chapter 1
Chapter 1

... within many theories. Rules for calculation can be accepted even when, as with probability, there may be different views as to the correct interpretation of the quantities being calculated. The interpretation of probability has been a matter of dispute for some time, although the terms of the disput ...
What Conditional Probability Also Could Not Be
What Conditional Probability Also Could Not Be

... offers in the spirit of my argument from vague probabilities is this: “Consider two infinitely thin darts thrown at the real line, with independent uniform probability distributions over the interval [0, 100]… Given that the first dart hits a large value, what is the probability that the second dar ...
Chapter 3 Notes Probability
Chapter 3 Notes Probability

Handling Uncertainties - using Probability Theory to
Handling Uncertainties - using Probability Theory to

Event-Based Probability Theory - Sirindhorn International Institute of
Event-Based Probability Theory - Sirindhorn International Institute of

Probability, Statistics, and Stochastic Processes
Probability, Statistics, and Stochastic Processes

EppDm4_09_09
EppDm4_09_09

... Let S denote the sample space of all possible choices of two balls from the urn, let B1 be the event that the first ball is blue, and let B2 be the event that the second ball is blue. ...
Lab #2
Lab #2

Some Inequalities and the Weak Law of Large Numbers
Some Inequalities and the Weak Law of Large Numbers

... Thus the chance that Y deviates from its mean by more than k standard deviations is less than 1/k 2 for any random variable Y . For k = 1 this is non-informative, since k 2 = 1. For k = 2 this is 0.25 – in other words, the chance is less than a quarter that Y deviates by more than 2 standard deviati ...
< 1 ... 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 ... 305 >

Probability interpretations



The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.
  • studyres.com © 2025
  • DMCA
  • Privacy
  • Terms
  • Report